Sunday 22 July 2007

Las emociones no son necesarias para juicios morales. Estudio en Nature, 21 marzo 2007

Thursday, March 22, 2007

Las emociones no son necesarias para juicios morales. Estudio en Nature, 21 marzo 2007

Letter

Nature advance online publication 21 March 2007 | doi:10.1038/nature05631; Received 3 November 2006; Accepted 17 February 2007; Published online 21 March 2007

Damage to the prefrontal cortex increases utilitarian moral judgements

Michael Koenigs1,5,6, Liane Young2,6, Ralph Adolphs1,3, Daniel Tranel1, Fiery Cushman2, Marc Hauser2 and Antonio Damasio1,4

  1. Department of Neurology, University of Iowa Hospitals and Clinics, Iowa City, Iowa 52242, USA
  2. Department of Psychology, Harvard University, Cambridge, Massachusetts 02138, USA
  3. Division of Humanities and Social Sciences and Division of Biology, California Institute of Technology, Pasadena, California 91125, USA
  4. Brain and Creativity Institute and Dornsife Center for Cognitive Neuroimaging, University of Southern California, Los Angeles, California 90089, USA
  5. Present address: National Institute of Neurological Disorders and Stroke, National Institutes of Health, Bethesda, Maryland 20892-1440, USA.
  6. These authors contributed equally to this work.

Correspondence to: Ralph Adolphs1,3 Correspondence and requests for materials should be addressed to R.A. (Email: radolphs@hss.caltech.edu).

Top

The psychological and neurobiological processes underlying moral judgement have been the focus of many recent empirical studies1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6, 7, 8, 9, 10, 11. Of central interest is whether emotions play a causal role in moral judgement, and, in parallel, how emotion-related areas of the brain contribute to moral judgement. Here we show that six patients with focal bilateral damage to the ventromedial prefrontal cortex (VMPC), a brain region necessary for the normal generation of emotions and, in particular, social emotions12, 13, 14, produce an abnormally 'utilitarian' pattern of judgements on moral dilemmas that pit compelling considerations of aggregate welfare against highly emotionally aversive behaviours (for example, having to sacrifice one person's life to save a number of other lives)7, 8. In contrast, the VMPC patients' judgements were normal in other classes of moral dilemmas. These findings indicate that, for a selective set of moral dilemmas, the VMPC is critical for normal judgements of right and wrong. The findings support a necessary role for emotion in the generation of those judgements.

The basis of our moral judgements has been a long-standing focus of philosophical inquiry and, more recently, active empirical investigation. In a departure from traditional rationalist approaches to moral cognition that emphasize the role of conscious reasoning from explicit principles15, modern accounts have proposed that emotional processes, conscious or unconscious, may also play an important role16, 17. Emotion-based accounts draw support from multiple lines of empirical work: studies of clinical populations reveal an association between impaired emotional processing and disturbances in moral behaviour1, 2, 3, 4; neuroimaging studies consistently show that tasks involving moral judgement activate brain areas known to process emotions5, 6, 7, 8, 9; and behavioural studies demonstrate that manipulation of affective state can alter moral judgements10, 11. However, neuroimaging studies do not settle whether putatively 'emotional' activations are a cause or consequence of moral judgement; behavioural studies in healthy individuals do not address the neural basis of moral judgement; and no clinical studies have specifically examined the moral judgements (as opposed to moral reasoning or moral behaviour) of patients with focal brain lesions. In brief, none of the existing studies establishes that brain areas integral to emotional processes are necessary for the generation of normal moral judgements. As a result, there remains a critical gap in the evidence relating moral judgement, emotion and the brain.

Investigating moral judgements in individuals with focal damage to the ventromedial prefrontal cortex (VMPC) provides a key test. The VMPC projects to basal forebrain and brainstem regions that execute bodily components of emotional responses18, and neurons within the VMPC encode the emotional value of sensory stimuli19. Patients with VMPC lesions exhibit generally diminished emotional responsivity and markedly reduced social emotions (for example, compassion, shame and guilt) that are closely associated with moral values1, 2, 12, 13, 14, 16, and also exhibit poorly regulated anger and frustration tolerance in certain circumstances20, 21. Despite these patent defects both in emotional response and emotion regulation, the capacities for general intelligence, logical reasoning, and declarative knowledge of social and moral norms are preserved20, 21, 22, 23. We selected a sample of six patients with adult-onset, focal bilateral VMPC lesions (Fig. 1) as well as both neurologically normal (NC) and brain-damaged comparison (BDC) subjects. Importantly, each of the VMPC patients had striking defects in social emotion but generally intact intellect and normal baseline mood (Tables 1 and 2, see also Supplementary Table 1). In particular, all six VMPC patients had impaired autonomic activity in response to emotionally charged pictures (Table 2), as well as severely diminished empathy, embarrassment and guilt (Table 2). All comparison subjects (NC and BDC) had intact emotional processing.

Figure 1: Lesion overlap of VMPC patients.
Figure 1 : Lesion overlap of VMPC patients. Unfortunately we are unable to provide accessible alternative text for this. If you require assistance to access this image, or to obtain a text description, please contact npg@nature.com

Lesions of the six VMPC patients displayed in mesial views and coronal slices. The colour bar indicates the number of overlapping lesions at each voxel.

High resolution image and legend (364K)



Subjects evaluated moral dilemmas designed to pit two competing considerations against one another. A paradigmatic dilemma of this type presents subjects with the choice of whether or not to sacrifice one person's life to save the lives of others. One consideration is a utilitarian calculation of how to maximize aggregate welfare, whereas the other is a strong emotional aversion to the proposed action. One model holds that endorsement of the proposed action (the utilitarian response) requires the subject to overcome an emotional response against inflicting direct harm to another person (a 'personal' harm7, 8). If emotional responses mediated by VMPC are indeed a critical influence on moral judgement, individuals with VMPC lesions should exhibit an abnormally high rate of utilitarian judgements on the emotionally salient, or 'personal', moral scenarios (for example, pushing one person off a bridge to stop a runaway boxcar from hitting five people), but a normal pattern of judgements on the less emotional, or 'impersonal', moral scenarios (for example, turning a runaway boxcar away from five people but towards one person). If, alternatively, emotion does not play a causal role in the generation of moral judgements but instead follows from the judgements24, 25, then individuals with emotion defects due to VMPC lesions should show a normal pattern of judgements on all scenarios.

To test for between-group differences in the probability of utilitarian responses given for each scenario type (non-moral, impersonal moral, personal moral), we used a logistic regression fitted with the generalized estimating equations method (Fig. 2). There were no significant differences between groups on the non-moral or impersonal moral scenarios (all P values >0.29, corrected for multiple comparisons). In contrast, for personal moral scenarios, the VMPC group was more likely to endorse the proposed action than either the NC group (odds ratio = 2.81; P = 0.04, corrected) or BDC group (odds ratio = 3.30; P = 0.006, corrected). There was no difference between the NC and BDC groups (odds ratio = 0.85; P = 0.68, uncorrected). These data indicate that the VMPC group's responses differed only for personal moral scenarios, suggesting that VMPC-mediated processes affect only those moral judgements involving emotionally salient actions.

Figure 2: Moral judgements for each scenario type.
Figure 2 : Moral judgements for each scenario type. Unfortunately we are unable to provide accessible alternative text for this. If you require assistance to access this image, or to obtain a text description, please contact npg@nature.com

Proportions of 'yes' judgements are shown for each subject group. Error bars indicate 95% confidence intervals. We used three classes of stimuli: non-moral scenarios (n = 18), impersonal moral scenarios (n = 11), and personal moral scenarios (n = 21). On personal moral scenarios, the frequency of endorsing 'yes' responses was significantly greater in the VMPC group than in either comparison group (P values <>High resolution image and legend (59K)


In a more fine-grained analysis, we examined response patterns within the personal moral scenarios. For seven out of the 21 personal moral scenarios, both comparison groups were at 100% agreement in their judgements. An additional eighth scenario elicited 100% agreement from the BDC group, and near-perfect agreement from the NC group (with only one participant deviating from the shared response). These eight scenarios were therefore classified as 'low-conflict' (for example, abandoning one's baby to avoid the burden of caring for it). The remaining 13 scenarios (none of which elicited 100% agreement from either comparison group) were classified as 'high-conflict' (for example, smothering one's baby to save a number of people). Reaction-time data support this distinction: response latencies in the NC group on high-conflict scenarios were significantly longer than on low-conflict scenarios (t-test with 19 degrees of freedom, t(19) = -3.63; P = 0.002).

Like the patients in the comparison groups, the VMPC patients uniformly rejected the proposed action in every one of the low-conflict scenarios (Fig. 3). In contrast, significant differences emerged for the high-conflict scenarios: the VMPC group was more likely to endorse the proposed action than either the NC (odds ratio = 4.70; P = 0.05, corrected) or BDC group (odds ratio = 5.38; P = 0.02, corrected), with no difference between the NC and BDC participants (odds ratio = 0.87; P = 0.77, uncorrected). Every high-conflict personal scenario elicited the same pattern: a greater proportion of the VMPC group endorsed the action than either comparison group.

Figure 3: Moral judgements on individual personal moral scenarios.
Figure 3 : Moral judgements on individual personal moral scenarios. Unfortunately we are unable to provide accessible alternative text for this. If you require assistance to access this image, or to obtain a text description, please contact npg@nature.com

Proportions of 'yes' judgements given by each subject group for each of the 21 personal moral scenarios. Individual scenarios (numbered 1–21 on the x axis) are ordered by increasing proportion of 'yes' responses given by the normal comparison group. Responses did not differ between subject groups for the low-conflict scenarios (left of the vertical line). The VMPC group made a greater proportion of 'yes' judgements than either comparison group for every one of the high-conflict scenarios (right of the vertical line).

High resolution image and legend (59K)

To recapitulate, VMPC patients' judgements differed from comparison subjects' only for the high-conflict personal moral dilemmas, all of which featured competing considerations of aggregate welfare on the one hand, and, on the other hand, harm to others that would normally evoke a strong social emotion. Low-conflict personal moral scenarios lacked this degree of competition. This difference probably accounts for the greater consensus and faster reaction times on low-conflict personal dilemmas in the comparison groups, and it can also account for the VMPC patients' pattern of judgements. Evidence suggests that knowledge of explicit social and moral norms is intact in individuals with VMPC damage21, 22. In the absence of an emotional reaction to harm of others in personal moral dilemmas, VMPC patients may rely on explicit norms endorsing the maximization of aggregate welfare and prohibiting the harming of others. This strategy would lead VMPC patients to a normal pattern of judgements on low-conflict personal dilemmas but an abnormal pattern of judgements on high-conflict personal dilemmas, precisely as was observed. The specificity of this result argues against a general deficit in the capacity for moral judgement following VMPC damage. Rather, VMPC seems to be critical only for moral dilemmas in which social emotions play a pivotal role in resolving moral conflict4, 8, 16, 17.

It is important to note that the effects of VMPC damage on emotion processing depend on context. In this study, the VMPC patients' abnormally high rate of utilitarian judgements is attributed to diminished social emotion, whereas in a recent study of the Ultimatum Game, theVMPC patients' abnormally high rate of rejection of unfair monetary offers was attributed to poorly controlled frustration, manifested as exaggerated anger20. These seemingly contradictory findings highlight two distinct aspects of emotion impairment that are due to VMPC damage. In most circumstances, VMPC patients exhibit generally blunted affect and a specific defect of social emotions, but in response to direct personal frustration or provocation, VMPC patients may exhibit short-temper, irritability, and anger. In the moral judgement task we report here, participants respond to hypothetical actions and outcomes that elicit social emotions related to concern for others. In the Ultimatum Game, in contrast, participants respond to unfair take-it-or-leave-it offers that trigger frustration. In brief, the tasks in the two studies are different in that the Ultimatum Game involves self-interest in a real behavioural setting, whereas the task in the present study focuses on the interest of others described in a hypothetical scenario.

To conclude, the present findings are consistent with a model in which a combination of intuitive/affective and conscious/rational mechanisms operate to produce moral judgements8, 22, 24, 25, 26, 27. Though the precise characterization of these potential systems awaits further work, the current results suggest that the VMPC is a critical neural substrate for the intuitive/affective but not for the conscious/rational system.

Top

Methods

Subjects

Six patients with bilateral, adult-onset damage to the VMPC and twelve brain-damaged comparison patients who had lesions that excluded structures thought to be important for emotions (VMPC, amygdala, insula, right somatosensory cortices) were recruited from the Patient Registry of the Division of Cognitive Neuroscience at the University of Iowa. Twelve healthy comparison subjects with no brain damage were recruited from the Iowa community. Groups were age-, gender- and ethnicity-matched. All participants gave written informed consent.

Neuroanatomical analysis

The neuroanatomical analysis of VMPC patients (Fig. 1) was based on magnetic resonance data for two subjects (those with lesions due to the surgical resection of orbital meningiomas) and on computerized tomography data for the other four subjects (with lesions due to rupture of an anterior communicating artery aneurysm). All neuroimaging data were obtained in the chronic epoch. Each patient's lesion was reconstructed in three dimensions using Brainvox28. Using the MAP-3 technique, the lesion contour for each patient was manually warped into a normal template brain. The overlap of lesions in this volume, calculated by the sum of n lesions overlapping on any single voxel, is colour-coded in Fig. 1.

Stimuli and task

Participants made judgements on a series of 50 hypothetical scenarios, which were adapted from a previously published set8. See the Supplementary Information for the full text of the actual scenarios used. Each scenario was presented as text through a series of three screens. The first two described the scenario and the third posed a question about a hypothetical action related to the scenario ("Would you...in order to...?"). Participants read and responded at their own pace, pressing an 'up' arrow key to advance from one screen to the next, and a 'yes' or 'no' button to indicate an answer to the question. 'Yes' responses always indicated commission of the proposed action. There was no time limit for reading the scenario description (screens 1 and 2). Participants had a maximum of 25 s to read the final question screen and respond.

We used three classes of stimuli: non-moral scenarios (n = 18), and two classes of moral scenarios subdivided according to the emotional reaction elicited by the proposed action: 'personal' (n = 21) or 'impersonal' (n = 11), as described previously7, 8. To validate this subdivision, an independent group of ten neurologically normal subjects rated the emotional salience of the actions proposed in the moral scenarios. The actions described in personal scenarios were rated as significantly more emotionally salient than the actions described in impersonal scenarios (means were 5.9 and 3.0 on a scale from 1 to 7, respectively; t(31) = -8.90, P <>

We further subdivided the personal moral scenarios into 'low-conflict' and 'high-conflict' on the basis of the reaction times and consensus produced on them by normal subjects. Reaction times on high-conflict scenarios were significantly longer than on low-conflict scenarios (t(19) = -3.63, P = 0.002). Importantly, low-conflict and high-conflict scenarios did not differ in their rated emotional salience (t(19) = -0.85, P = 0.41).

Top

References

  1. Eslinger, P. J., Grattan, L. M. & Damasio, A. R. Developmental consequences of childhood frontal lobe damage. Arch. Neurol. 49, 764–769 (1992) | PubMed | ISI | ChemPort |
  2. Anderson, S. W., Bechara, A., Damasio, H., Tranel, D. & Damasio, A. R. Impairment of social and moral behavior related to early damage in human prefrontal cortex. Nature Neurosci. 2, 1032–1037 (1999)
  3. Blair, R. J. R. A cognitive developmental approach to morality: investigating the psychopath. Cognition 57, 1–29 (1995)
  4. Mendez, M. F., Anderson, E. & Shapira, J. S. An investigation of moral judgment in frontotemporal dementia. Cogn. Behav. Neurol. 18, 193–197 (2005)
  5. Moll, J., de Oliveira-Souza, R., Bramati, I. E. & Grafman, J. Functional networks in emotional moral and nonmoral social judgments. Neuroimage 16, 696–703 (2002) | Article | PubMed | ISI |
  6. Heekeren, H. R., Wartenburger, I., Schmidt, H., Schwintowski, H. P. & Villringer, A. An fMRI study of simple ethical decision-making. Neuroreport 14, 1215–1219 (2003) | Article | PubMed | ISI |
  7. Greene, J. D., Sommerville, R. B., Nystrom, L. E., Darley, J. M. & Cohen, J. D. An fMRI investigation of emotional engagement in moral judgment. Science 293, 2105–2108 (2001) | Article | PubMed | ISI | ChemPort |
  8. Greene, J. D., Nystrom, L. E., Engell, A. D., Darley, J. M. & Cohen, J. D. The neural bases of cognitive conflict and control in moral judgment. Neuron 44, 389–400 (2004) | Article | PubMed | ISI | ChemPort |
  9. Luo, Q. et al. The neural basis of implicit moral attitude–An IAT study using event-related fMRI. Neuroimage 30, 1449–1457 (2006)
  10. Wheatley, T. & Haidt, J. Hypnotic disgust makes moral judgments more severe. Psychol. Sci. 16, 780–784 (2005)
  11. Valdesolo, P. & DeSteno, D. Manipulations of emotional context shape moral judgment. Psychol. Sci. 17, 476–477 (2006)
  12. Damasio, A. R., Tranel, D. & Damasio, H. Individuals with sociopathic behavior caused by frontal damage fail to respond autonomically to social stimuli. Behav. Brain Res. 41, 81–94 (1990) | Article | PubMed | ISI | ChemPort |
  13. Damasio, A. R. Looking for Spinoza: Joy, Sorrow, and the Feeling Brain (Harcourt, New York, 2003)
  14. Beer, J. S., Heerey, E. H., Keltner, D., Scabini, D. & Knight, R. T. The regulatory function of self-conscious emotion: Insights from patients with orbitofrontal damage. J. Pers. Soc. Psychol. 85, 594–604 (2003) | Article | PubMed | ISI |
  15. Kohlberg, L. Essays on Moral Development Vol. 1 The Philosophy of Moral Development (Harper Row, New York, 1981)
  16. Damasio, A. R. Descartes' Error: Emotion, Reason, and the Human Brain (Penguin, New York, 1994)
  17. Haidt, J. The emotional dog and its rational tail: A social intuitionist approach to moral judgment. Psychol. Rev. 108, 814–834 (2001) | Article | PubMed | ISI | ChemPort |
  18. Ongur, D. & Price, J. L. The organization of networks within the orbital and medial prefrontal cortex of rats, monkeys and humans. Cereb. Cortex 10, 206–219 (2000) | Article | PubMed | ISI | ChemPort |
  19. Rolls, E. The orbitofrontal cortex and reward. Cereb. Cortex 3, 284–294 (2000)
  20. Koenigs, M. & Tranel, D. Irrational economic decision-making after ventromedial prefrontal damage: evidence from the ultimatum game. J. Neurosci. 27, 951–956 (2007)
  21. Anderson, S. W., Barrash, J., Bechara, A. & Tranel, D. Impairments of emotion and real-world complex behavior following childhood- or adult-onset damage to ventromedial prefrontal cortex. J. Int. Neuropsychol. Soc. 12, 224–235 (2006)
  22. Saver, J. L. & Damasio, A. R. Preserved access and processing of social knowledge in a patient with acquired sociopathy due to ventromedial frontal damage. Neuropsychologia 29, 1241–1249 (1991) | Article | PubMed | ISI | ChemPort |
  23. Burgess, P. W. et al. The case for the development and use of "ecologically valid" measures of executive functions in experimental and clinical neuropsychology. J. Int. Neuropsychol. Soc. 12, 194–209 (2006)
  24. Hauser, M. D. Moral Minds: How Nature Designed our Universal Sense of Right and Wrong (Ecco/Harper Collins, New York, 2006)
  25. Mikhail, J. Rawls' Linguistic Analogy. PhD thesis, Cornell Univ. (2000)
  26. Cushman, F. A., Young, L. L. & Hauser, M. D. The role of conscious reasoning and intuition in moral judgments: Testing three principles of permissible harm. Psychol. Sci. 17, 1082–1089 (2006)
  27. Hauser, M. D., Cushman, F. A., Young, L. L., Jin, K-X. & Mikhail, J. A dissociation between moral judgments and justifications. Mind Language 22, 1–21 (2006)
  28. Frank, R. J., Damasio, H. & Grabowski, T. J. Brainvox: an interactive, multimodal visualization and analysis system for neuroanatomical imaging. Neuroimage 5, 13–30 (1997) | Article | PubMed | ISI | ChemPort |
  29. Barrash, J. & Anderson, S. W. The Iowa Rating Scales of Personality Change (Department of Neurology, Univ. Iowa, Iowa, 1993)
Top

Supplementary Information

Supplementary information accompanies this paper.

Top

Acknowledgements

We thank H. Damasio for making available neuroanatomical analyses of lesion patients and for preparing Fig. 1. We thank all participants for their participation in the experiments and R. Saxe for comments on the manuscript. This work was supported by grants from the National Institutes of Health, the National Science Foundation, the Gordon and Betty Moore Foundation, and the Guggenheim Foundation.

---o----o----o----o----o---o---o---o---o---o---o---o---o---o---o---o

Impaired emotional processing affects moral judgements

  • 13:07 22 March 2007
  • NewScientist.com news service
  • Roxanne Khamsi

Mr Spock, the fictional Vulcan famously logical and lacking in emotion, sacrificed himself for his comrades in the movie Star Trek II: The Wrath of Khan with the following words to Captain Kirk: "The needs of the many outweigh the needs of the few, or the one…"

Now, revealing new research shows that people with damage to a key emotion-processing region of the brain also make moral decisions based on the greater good of the community, unclouded by concerns over harming an individual.

It is the first study to demonstrate how emotion impacts moral judgement and sheds light on why people often act out of respect for an individual rather than choosing to act in a more logical, utilitarian way. The findings could cause a rethink in how society determines a "moral good", and challenge the 18th-century philosophies of Immanuel Kant and David Hume.

Antonio Damasio at the University of Southern California in Los Angeles, US, and colleagues recruited 30 people for their experiment. Six of the subjects had suffered damage to a region in the front of the brain known as the ventromedial prefrontal cortex (VMPC), which regulates emotions. The participants had this brain injury as a result of an aneurism or tumour growth in the VMPC region.

Twelve participants in the study had damage to other parts of the brain but not the VMPC. And the remaining 12 subjects had no brain injury whatsoever.

"Utilitarian" action

The researchers presented participants with various scenarios (scroll to the bottom for several examples) and asked them to make decisions based on the information provided. Some of the situations involved moral decision-making. For example, subjects had to say whether they would throw a person in front of a train if doing so would stop the train from barrelling into five workmen, killing all five.

In such a situation, most people would find it morally unacceptable to push someone to his or her death – even if doing so would save the lives of others. And this was the reaction of the healthy participants or those that had injury to brain regions excluding the VMPC. But people with damage to the VMPC showed a willingness to take this type of "utilitarian" action.

"You have one group that is ready to endorse what we would regard as an overly utilitarian judgment and the other far less" willing to do so, explains Damasio. He notes that the patients with VMPC damage generally made the same decisions as their control counterparts when it came to non-moral scenarios.

Subtle scenarios

Notably, people with VMPC damage were just as likely as their counterparts to endorse "impersonal" moral decisions that involved indirectly putting strangers at risk for the greater good. These impersonal moral scenarios involved, for example, encouraging the use of a vaccine that would protect the public but cause an adverse reaction in a few individuals.

These results suggest that emotions play a crucial role in moral decisions involving personal contact – but not in moral judgments involving distant, indirect impacts on other people. "What's beautiful to me is how subtly different the situations are," says Marc Hauser at Harvard University in Cambridge, Massachusetts, US, one of the researchers involved.

The finding that some moral judgments involve emotions while others do not supports the supposedly diametrically opposed thinking of philosophers Immanuel Kant and David Hume.

"It means both Kant and Hume are right. Philosophers will have a fit because they like to choose sides," says Frans de Waal at Emory University in Atlanta, Georgia, US. Hume believed that people could be motivated to make proper moral decisions based on their sympathy for others. Kant, meanwhile, warned that moral judgments might be corrupted by emotions.

Personal dignity

Philip Kitcher, who teaches philosophy at Columbia University in New York, US, notes that the study of brain damaged individuals presents a unique challenge to Kant's philosophy. While Kant cautioned against the corruptive influence of emotions, he also argued that individuals have personal dignity, which must be respected.

Yet in the new study, subjects who had impaired emotion processing due to VPMC damage showed the least concern for individual dignity in the personal moral dilemmas that involved directly harming another person to save others. This provides strong biological evidence that emotions enable us to respect individual dignity, says Kitcher.

"Emotions are an anchor for our moral systems. If you remove that anchor you can end up anywhere," says de Waal.

Examples of scenarios used in the experiment:

Non-Moral Scenario: Investment Offer

You are at home one day when the mail arrives. You receive a letter from a reputable corporation that provides financial services. They have invited you to invest in a mutual fund, beginning with an initial investment of one thousand dollars.

As it happens, you are familiar with this particular mutual fund. It has not performed very well over the past few years, and, based on what you know, there is no reason to think that it will perform any better in the future.

Would you invest a thousand dollars in this mutual fund in order to make money?

Impersonal Moral Scenario: Standard Trolley

You are at the wheel of a runaway trolley quickly approaching a fork in the tracks. On the tracks extending to the left is a group of five railway workmen. On the tracks extending to the right is a single railway workman.

If you do nothing the trolley will proceed to the left, causing the deaths of the five workmen. The only way to avoid the deaths of these workmen is to hit a switch on your dashboard that will cause the trolley to proceed to the right, causing the death of the single workman.

Would you hit the switch in order to avoid the deaths of the five workmen?

Personal Moral Scenario: Submarine

You are the captain of a military submarine travelling underneath a large iceberg. An onboard explosion has caused you to lose most of your oxygen supply and has injured one of your crew who is quickly losing blood. The injured crew member is going to die from his wounds no matter what happens.

The remaining oxygen is not sufficient for the entire crew to make it to the surface. The only way to save the other crew members is to shoot dead the injured crew member so that there will be just enough oxygen for the rest of the crew to survive.

Would you kill the fatally injured crew member in order to save the lives of the remaining crew members?

Personal Moral Scenario: Infection

Someone you know has AIDS and plans to infect others, some of whom will die. Your only options are to let it happen or to kill the person.

Do you pull the trigger?

Journal reference: Nature (DOI: 10.1038/nature05631)

---o----o----o----o----o---o---o---o---o---o---o---o---o---o---o---o

Lisboa

Quinta, 22 de Março de 2007
Edição Papel


Decisões morais falham se não houver emoção



Filomena Naves

É um cenário teórico extremo: alguém com uma doença infecciosa e mortal decide infectar propositadamente outras pessoas, muitas das quais morrerão, e a única hipótese de evitar que isso aconteça é matar essa pessoa. Confrontada com um dilema desta natureza, a maioria das pessoas hesita, ou diz que não o faria, mesmo pensando que em teoria devia fazê-lo. No entanto, doentes com uma lesão muito localizada no cérebro são um caso à parte. E a sua escolha num cenário deste tipo é apenas a escolha lógica, sem as emoções a desencadear hesitações.

Conclusão: as emoções desempenham um papel causal importante nas nossas decisões morais. Este é o resultado da mais recente investigação sobre as emoções e o cérebro realizada por uma equipa de neurologistas norte-americanos co--liderada pelo neurocientista português António Damásio. Publicado hoje na Nature, este estudo é também o primeiro a demonstrar esta função das emoções. Sem elas, algumas decisões morais mantêm a lógica, mas resultam frias e inumanas.

A lesão cerebral em causa localiza-se no cortex pré-frontal, numa zona chamada VMPC (ventromedial prefrontal cortex, em inglês), e para avaliar o seu papel nas decisões morais a equipa montou uma experiência em que participaram 30 pessoas, dividas em três grupos. Um com este tipo de lesão cerebral, outro com lesões noutras regiões do cérebro e outro ainda sem qualquer lesão cerebral. Todos os participantes foram sujeitos a um questionário com uma série de cenários que envolviam escolhas como a já referida.

"A maioria das pessoas sem esta lesão específica fica dividida. Mas estes indivíduos [com lesão na VMPC] parecem não sentir o conflito", explicou António Damásio, que dirige o Brain and Creativity Institute na University of Southern California, em Los Angeles, nos EUA.

"É incrível como esta lesão é selectiva", notou Marc Hauser, professor de psicologia em Harvard e co-autor do estudo, sublinhando que ela "interfere com a capacidade de decisão moral quando uma acção negativa entra em conflito com o resultado utilitário". Um sentimento de aversão impede os seres humanos de fazer mal uns aos outros. Com esta lesão cerebral, esse mecanismo deixa de existir.








No comments: